In one of his typically short but lucid essays, David Furley lists the view that the world is eternal as one of the main ingredients in what he calls the cosmological crisis in antiquity1. By «crisis», Furley means choice. His view is that the history of Greek cosmology is best understood in light of the choice between «two fundamentally and comprehensively different ways of understanding the universe»–in other words, two incompatible cosmological outlooks. Furley calls them «Atomism» and «Aristotelianism». Evidently, he uses the label «Aristotelianism» in a generous way. For one thing, the view that the world is eternal enjoyed success far beyond the narrow boundaries of the Aristotelian tradition.For another,Aristotle defended a specific version of this view. If therefore we want to continue to speak of Aristotelianism in connection with the reception of this view in antiquity, we need to be as clear as possible on the following point: we are using this label to refer to a constellation of different positions. An interesting question for us is how much of Aristotle’s original view is left in these later positions. I will return to this question in due course.

The Reception of Aristotle’s Physics in Antiquity: Ps-Ocellus and the Doctrine of the Eternity of the World in the Late Hellenistic and Early Post-Hellenistic World (2nd and 1st Century BC) / A. Falcon. - In: PHILOSOPHIA. - ISSN 1105-2120. - 46:(2016), pp. 154-169.

The Reception of Aristotle’s Physics in Antiquity: Ps-Ocellus and the Doctrine of the Eternity of the World in the Late Hellenistic and Early Post-Hellenistic World (2nd and 1st Century BC)

A. Falcon
2016

Abstract

In one of his typically short but lucid essays, David Furley lists the view that the world is eternal as one of the main ingredients in what he calls the cosmological crisis in antiquity1. By «crisis», Furley means choice. His view is that the history of Greek cosmology is best understood in light of the choice between «two fundamentally and comprehensively different ways of understanding the universe»–in other words, two incompatible cosmological outlooks. Furley calls them «Atomism» and «Aristotelianism». Evidently, he uses the label «Aristotelianism» in a generous way. For one thing, the view that the world is eternal enjoyed success far beyond the narrow boundaries of the Aristotelian tradition.For another,Aristotle defended a specific version of this view. If therefore we want to continue to speak of Aristotelianism in connection with the reception of this view in antiquity, we need to be as clear as possible on the following point: we are using this label to refer to a constellation of different positions. An interesting question for us is how much of Aristotle’s original view is left in these later positions. I will return to this question in due course.
No
English
Settore M-FIL/07 - Storia della Filosofia Antica
Articolo
Comitato scientifico
Ricerca di base
Pubblicazione scientifica
2016
46
154
169
16
Pubblicato
Periodico con rilevanza internazionale
Aderisco
info:eu-repo/semantics/article
The Reception of Aristotle’s Physics in Antiquity: Ps-Ocellus and the Doctrine of the Eternity of the World in the Late Hellenistic and Early Post-Hellenistic World (2nd and 1st Century BC) / A. Falcon. - In: PHILOSOPHIA. - ISSN 1105-2120. - 46:(2016), pp. 154-169.
reserved
Prodotti della ricerca::01 - Articolo su periodico
1
262
Article (author)
Periodico senza Impact Factor
A. Falcon
File in questo prodotto:
File Dimensione Formato  
12. A Falcon, Ps-Ocellus.pdf

accesso riservato

Tipologia: Publisher's version/PDF
Dimensione 115.52 kB
Formato Adobe PDF
115.52 kB Adobe PDF   Visualizza/Apri   Richiedi una copia
Pubblicazioni consigliate

I documenti in IRIS sono protetti da copyright e tutti i diritti sono riservati, salvo diversa indicazione.

Utilizza questo identificativo per citare o creare un link a questo documento: https://hdl.handle.net/2434/700408
Citazioni
  • ???jsp.display-item.citation.pmc??? ND
  • Scopus ND
  • ???jsp.display-item.citation.isi??? ND
social impact